This is the html version of the file https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/edit/10.4324/9781315564296-1/compassion-paul-gilbert.
Google automatically generates html versions of documents as we crawl the web.
Page 1
Chapter 1
Compassion
Definitions and controversies
Paul Gilbert
Compassion is clearly linked to the evolution of caring behaviour (Gilbert,
1989/2016, 2009, 2015a, 2015b; Keltner, Kogan, Piff & Saturn, 2014;
Mayseless, 2016), altruism (Preston, 2013; Goetz, Keltner & Simon-Thomas,
2010; Ricard, 2015) and prosocial behaviour in general (Bierhoff, 2005;
Brown & Brown, 2015; Penner, Dovidio, Piliavin & Schroeder, 2005). The
last 20 years have seen increasing research into the nature and benefits of all
these. For compassion, these include a range of effects on psychological pro-
cesses (Jazaieri et al., 2013; Keltner et al., 2014; Singer & Bolz, 2012), social
relationships (Cozolino, 2006; Crocker & Canevello, 2012; Penner et al.,
2005) and physiological processes (Klimecki, Leiberg, Ricard & Singer, 2014;
Kogan et al., 2014; Simon-Thomas et al., 2011; Weng et al., 2013) that extend
to genetic expression (Slavich & Cole, 2013; Slavic & Conway, Chapter 9,
this volume). Hoge et al. (2013) found that women with experience of
loving-kindness meditation had longer relative telomere length than controls
(see also Fredrickson et al., 2013). Compassionate motives benefit social rela-
tionships and well-being, whereas ego self-focused motives do not (Crocker &
Canevello, 2012). Compassion has become the focus for psychotherapeutic
interventions with increasing evidence for its effectiveness (Gilbert, 2000, 2010,
2015c; Hofmann, Grossman & Hinton, 2011; Kirby & Gilbert, Chapter 15,
this volume; Leaviss & Uttley, 2015; Neff & Germer, 2013). In addition, all the
chapters of this book address these themes too. However, despite this progress
there remains controversy and discussion around the actual nature of compassion,
its definition and constituents. This chapter explores some of these controversies.
Issues of definition: what’s in a word?
We can only understand phenomena by agreeing a set of properties by which
phenomena will be known. So, for example, we can distinguish between a chair,
an elephant, a tiger and a cat by agreeing a set of qualities and properties that
belong to each and those that are specific. Hence, they share qualities as four-
legged things, but not of being living organisms. We can then distinguish between
an elephant, a tiger and a cat and then finally between a tiger and a cat, and even
different breeds of cat. Each subdivision has more and more overlapping features,

Page 2
4 Paul Gilbert
but also more fine-grained distinctions. This is important in areas like compassion
too which are easily fused with concepts such as altruism, benevolence, hearted-
ness, prosociality, kindness and love. Sometimes it’s the fine-grained distinctions
that are important. Second, as the late Prof Kendell (1975) used to drum into us
clinical trainees in Edinburgh in the 1970s, there is no such ‘thing’ as depres-
sion, anxiety or paranoia as rarefied states. Rather there are a set of phenomena
(signs and symptoms) that we agree may cluster/fit together and we will give
labels to, so that we can agree what we are discussing when we use the label.
So too, the definition of compassion will depend upon the shared properties we
give to this concept and its differentiation from similar concepts. Third, definition
problems can plague psychological research because of the insufficient atten-
tion it gives to functions. For example, shame and guilt, envy and jealousy, are
frequently used interchangeably when they are in fact very different, with very
different evolutionary histories, competencies, functions and focus (Gilbert, 1989,
1998, 2005, 2009). So, as will be discussed, although there are many general ideas
around what compassion is, currently there is no clear agreement about what the
specific attributes of compassion are. Let’s take a look at the range.
Defining compassion
One origin of the word compassion is from the Latin compati, meaning ‘to
suffer with’. However, words change their meanings with use over time and across
cultures and this is certainly the case for the word compassion. For example, to
‘suffer with’ need not imply a compassionate motivation to do anything about it.
Today ‘to suffer with or on behalf of’ might be more closely related to what we
now call sympathy (Eisenberg, VanSchyndel & Hofer, 2015) or empathy (Batson,
2009). Aristotle argued that we only had compassion if we thought the suffering
of another was nontrivial; to use one of his examples, ‘we would not have com-
passion for the upset of an emperor who’d lost a shipment of Larks tongues he’d
ordered for his party!’ (Nassbaum, 2003). Aristotle also thought that a sense of
deserve influenced compassion, and third that we would have to have some sense
of that suffering; that we could imagine ourselves in their situation (Nassbaum,
2003). So the seriousness of suffering, sense of deserve and empathy texture com-
passion for Aristotle. Buddhist scholars would not see these qualities as central.
In regard to dictionary definitions there are quite a variety. The Oxford
Dictionary (2016) suggests that compassion is ‘Sympathetic pity and concern for
the sufferings or misfortunes of others’. Teaching in France, Germany and Italy,
colleagues inform me that ‘compassion’ is a difficult word to translate and can
indeed be linked to pity. This is obviously a problem because pity is a very differ-
ent process altogether and involves a sense of looking down on others (Nassbaum,
2003). This is a good example where misunderstanding about the use of a word
can lead to heated debates and serious confusions. Schopenhauer (1788–1860),
who was deeply influenced by Buddhist thought, and one of the first Western
thinkers to introduce compassion into philosophy, argued that compassion was

Page 3
Compassion: definitions and controversies 5
one of the highest and most important qualities of humanity. Neither self-interest,
nor duty, social conformity nor fear of punishment could, in his view, be a source
of genuine morality (Cartwright, 1988). However, Nietzsche wrote a number of
significant critiques of Schopenhauer arguing that compassion is a poor source
for moral development. The problem is, as Cartwright (1988) observed, these two
philosophers were talking at cross purposes because of poor word definition:
[B]ecause Schopenhauer and Nietzsche refer to two different emotions by
the German noun ‘Mitleid’; that it is best to understand Schopenhauer’s
conception of ‘Mitleid’ as ‘compassion’ and Nietzsche’s as ‘pity’. I shall
argue that compassion is significantly (and morally) different from pity in
ways that make Schopenhauer’s Mitleids-Moral immune to this element of
Nietzsche’s critique.
(p. 1)
This confusion of concepts remains, especially in translations, and may help
explain why, at times, compassion is regarded as unhelpful (Who wants to be
pitied?), or even as a weakness. In contrast, the Cambridge University Dictionary
(2016) suggests compassion is ‘a strong feeling of sympathy and sadness for the
suffering or bad luck of others and a wish to help them’. Here, ‘pity’ is absent
and is replaced with ‘sympathy’ and ‘feelings of sadness’, and the ‘wish to be
helpful’ is also added. The concept of sympathy or ‘natural sympathy’, as David
Hume called it, as underpinning human benevolence, is prevalent in many early
philosophical texts. This definition also has the idea of a specific ‘feeling’ in
compassion that stimulates motivated helping behaviour. In Goetz et al.’s (2010)
major review of some of the evolutionary and historical origins of compassion
they also place feeling centre stage:
We define compassion as the feeling that arises in witnessing another’s
suffering and that motivates a subsequent desire to help. This definition con-
ceptualizes compassion as an affective state defined by a specific subjective
feeling, and it differs from treatments of compassion as an attitude . . . This
definition also clearly differentiates compassion from empathy, which refers
to the vicarious experience of another’s emotions.
(p. 351; italics added)
They also distinguish compassion from distress, sadness and love. As helpful and
as detailed as this review is, there is a difference in defining compassion as a feel�
ing state rather than a motivational state, and it is important not to confuse motives
with emotions (Deckers, 2014; Gilbert, 2015a, Weiner, 1992). Indeed, Ekman
(2016) surveyed researchers who study emotion. While 91% saw anger and 90%
saw anxiety as basic emotions, compassion was rated one of the lowest with only
20% agreeing that compassion is an emotion. Without an evolved caring motiva-
tion system there would be no emotions arising to signals of suffering/distress.

Page 4
6 Paul Gilbert
It is the motivation system that necessitates emotions in contexts, and those emotions
may well then stimulate motivated actions (Gilbert, Chapter 3, this volume).
It is also unclear what the feeling state of compassion is. For example, what
is the emotion when rushing into a burning house to save a child, consoling a
recently bereaved or dying friend or fighting for human justice? It is likely that in
the first case the feeling states/emotions are of urgency and anxiety, in the second
sadness and sorrow, and in the third case a degree of anger at injustice. It’s not
the emotions that unite them, but the motivation to pay attention (on suffering and
needs) and the motivation and intention to do something about it. That intention
can be present even when people are not thinking about it or are not activated.
Note too that compassion can represent blends of emotions. For example, a doctor
is struck by the suffering of the Ebola virus and dedicates his/her life, working
long hours, to finding a cure. Emotions here may be a blend of anger that such
viruses exist in the world, sadness for the suffering caused and the way people die
from it, and anxiety that if it gets out into the world it could even reach his/her
own family. In addition, whereas emotions wax and wane, a motivation can guide
behaviour for the whole of one’s life.
The facial expressions of compassion can also differ according to context.
The facial expressions we may have when consoling somebody in physical pain
may be different to being with their grief or anger. The facial expression of a
therapist meeting a patient for the first time and wishing to present themselves as
compassionate, trustworthy and a safe listener will be different from compassion-
ate expressions as different aspects of the story unfold. Whereas compassionate,
kind and trustworthy faces are usually perceived as friendly, affiliative, happy
and positive, such facial expressions may be less positively experienced when
the viewer is in pain (Gerdes, Wieser, Alpers, Strack & Pauli, 2012; Godinho,
Frot, Perchet, Magnin & Garcia-Larrea, 2008). When asked to pose compassion
faces people automatically create soft expressions with gentle smiles of softness,
friendliness and signals on being ‘safe’, kindness and gentleness (McEwan et al.,
2014). Furthermore, it is now recognised that although compassion is seen as a
positive act, it actually engages aversive emotions which arise when we are in
touch with suffering (Condon & Barrett, 2013). So context is crucial.
The Free Dictionary definition (2016) suggests compassion is a ‘Deep aware-
ness of the suffering of another accompanied by the wish to relieve it’. In this
definition there is no pity, sympathy or ‘specific feeling’ aspect like sadness or
sorrow, but a focus on ‘deep awareness’ with (again) a motivation (the wish) to
do something about it. This definition gets closer to the traditional philosophical
and contemplative traditions of compassion, as we will see.
The contemplative traditions and the multifaceted approach: Many approaches
to compassion see it as multifaceted, although they do not always agree on what
those facets are. Buddhist scholar Geshe Thupten Jinpa (translator to the Dalai
Lama) and colleagues, who developed the Stanford compassion cultivation train-
ing, define compassion as:

Page 5
Compassion: definitions and controversies 7
[A] multidimensional process comprised of four key components: (1) an
awareness of suffering (cognitive/empathic awareness), (2) sympathetic con-
cern related to being emotionally moved by suffering (affective component),
(3) a wish to see the relief of that suffering (intention), and (4) a responsive-
ness or readiness to help relieve that suffering (motivational).
(Jazaieri et al., 2013)
Mindfulness and compassion thinkers Christina Feldman and Willem Kuyken
(2011) also highlight the multifaceted textures of compassion. They suggest that:
Compassion is the acknowledgment that not all pain can be ‘fixed’ or ‘solved’
but all suffering is made more approachable in a landscape of compassion.
Compassion is a multi-textured response to pain, sorrow and anguish. It
includes kindness, empathy, generosity and acceptance. The strands of cour-
age, tolerance, equanimity are equally woven into the cloth of compassion.
Above all, compassion is the capacity to open to the reality of suffering and
to aspire to its healing.
(p. 143)
They go on to add:
Compassion is an orientation of mind that recognises pain and the universality
of pain in human experience and the capacity to meet that pain with kindness,
empathy, equanimity and patience. While self-compassion orients to our own
experience, compassion extends this orientation to others’ experience.
(p. 145)
Kuyken and his colleagues offer a more specific listing from their major, more
recent literature review (Strauss et al., 2016).
[W]e propose a new definition of compassion as a cognitive, affective, and
behavioural process consisting of the following five elements that refer to both
self – and other – compassion: (1) Recognizing suffering; (2) Understanding
the universality of suffering in human experience; (3) Feeling empathy for
the person suffering and connecting with the distress (emotional resonance);
(4) Tolerating uncomfortable feelings aroused in response to the suffering
person (e.g. distress, anger, fear) so remaining open to and accepting of the
person suffering; and (5) Motivation to act/acting to alleviate suffering.
(p. 19)
Dutton, Workman and Hardin (2014), who have done considerable work on com-
passion in organisations, relate compassion to four core aspects that also touch on
cognitive, affective and behavioural processes: (1) noticing/attending to another’s

Page 6
8 Paul Gilbert
suffering, (2) sensemaking or meaning making related to suffering; (3) feelings
that resemble empathic concern, and (4) actions aimed at easing the suffering.
Emotions researcher Paul Ekman (2014), who worked with the Dalai Lama,
suggests four dimensions of compassion: (1) empathic compassion (being in
touch with the feelings of suffering of others); (2) action compassion (taking
action to alleviate suffering); (3) concerned compassion (based on a motivation
for helping); and (4) aspirational compassion (linked to a more cognitive desire
to develop compassion).
Into the mix of what compassion is, Neff (2003) focused on self-compassion and
defines it as follows:
Self-compassion . . . involves being touched by and open to one’s own
suffering, not avoiding or disconnecting from it, generating the desire to alle-
viate one’s suffering and to heal oneself with kindness. Self-compassion also
involves offering nonjudgmental understanding to one’s pain, inadequacies
and failures, so that one’s experience is seen as part of the larger human
experience.
(p. 87)
She also went on to suggest there are three bipolar dimensions that underpin self-
compassion: self-kindness (in contrast to self-judgment and self-criticism); shared
common humanity (in contrast to feeling isolated and alone and the only one);
and mindfulness (in contrast to self-absorption and rumination). These constructs
and resulting measures have not been without controversy (L�pez et al., 2015;
Muris & Petrocchi, 2016) as Neff herself recognises (Neff, Whittakar & Karl, in
press). They are different to, say, a competencies focus (see Gilbert, Chapter 3,
this volume). As Neff (2003, 2011) makes clear, what sits behind her approach
is to consider a ‘self-compassionate frame of mind’ as a way to help people cope
with difficult life circumstances and especially with self-criticism (see Germer &
Barnhofer, Chapter 4, this volume).
Different again is Armstrong’s (2011) focus on the roots of compassion in the
golden rule of Confucius: ‘Do unto others as you would be done to’, or more neg-
atively ‘don’t do things to other people you would not like them to do to yourself’.
This has inspired the Charter for Compassion – designed to spread compassion
values and behaviour through communitie – which is now a major world move-
ment (see http://www.charterforcompassion.org).
Motivation approaches
Listing potential characteristics of compassion, a kind of diagnostic approach can
be supported with a functional approach that focuses on motivation. Motivation
is then not ‘one of’ the characteristics. ‘It underpins signs or symptoms’ of com-
passion; it is the main show that generates the core characteristics. Motivation

Page 7
Compassion: definitions and controversies 9
underpins not just action but also being prepared to pay attention to suffering.
Buddhist scholar Mathieu Ricard (2015) suggests that compassion is a form of
altruism, made up of a range of sub-attributes, abilities and skills including sym-
pathy, empathy and commitment. But at its heart, compassion is a deeply felt wish
for others to be free of suffering, the causes of suffering, and to flourish and to
find happiness (personal communication, 2012). This focus highlights motivation
as ‘the wish’ (motive) for the alleviation of suffering.
Interestingly, compassion (motivation) hasn’t been that clearly distinguished
from altruism. For example, Preston (2013) suggests altruism as an almost identical
process:
Altruistic responding is defined as any form of helping that applies when the
giver is motivated to assist a specific target after perceiving their distress or
need . . . Altruistic responding further narrows these classifications to only
include cases where the motivation to respond is fomented by direct or indirect
perception of the other’s distress or need . . . This excludes cases that emerged
later in time or include diverse processes, such as cooperation or helping influ-
enced by strategic goals, social norms, display rules, or mate signaling.
(p. 1307; italics added)
Here, there has to be a cost of helping to the self that might not be the case for
compassion. This also is a different take on altruism than say Ricard (2015). The
Dalai Lama (2001) also links compassion to motivation (a wish):
What is compassion? Compassion is the wish that others be free of suffering. It
is by means of compassion that we aspire to attain enlightenment. It is compas-
sion that inspires us to engage in the virtuous practices that lead to Buddhahood.
We must therefore devote ourselves to developing compassion.
(p. 91; italics added)
He also distinguishes between these wishes:
Just as compassion is the wish that all sentient beings be free of suffering,
loving-kindness is the wish that all may enjoy happiness.
(p. 96)
So compassion also acts as an ‘inspiration’. There is a clear distinction between
loving-kindness (happiness focused) and compassion cultivation, as is captured
in the concept of Bodhichitta (Gilbert & Choden, 2013; Tsering, 2005). Here
again definitions are tricky because actually ‘metta’ means friendliness or open-
heartedness, not ‘love’ as understood in Western psychology. These kinds of
mistranslations and merging of concepts have caused difficulties for compassion,
which can sometimes be confused with love (Gilbert & Choden, 2013; Goetz
et al., 2010). In the West, love implies liking trust and affection, but in reality

Page 8
10 Paul Gilbert
deep-courageous compassion is for those we may not know, may not like, trust
or feel affection for. Indeed, the Dalai Lama (1995) suggests that if we just have
compassion for people we love this is not real compassion! ‘Your love and com-
passion towards your friends is in many cases actually attachment. This feeling
is not based on the realization that all beings have an equal right to be happy and
overcome suffering’ (p. 63). When it comes to compassion for those whom we
do not like, or who may threaten or harm us, then understanding courageous and
assertive compassion, and its distinction from submissiveness and compliance, is
crucial (Catarino, Gilbert, McEwan & Bai�o, 2014).
An insight that drives compassion in the Tibetan Buddhist traditions is insight
into the fact that suffering naturally arises from the life process itself, including
the impermanence of all things and our graspings and aversions (Dalai Lama,
1995; Tsering, 2005). Mindful compassion helps us to have insight into the illu-
sory nature of the self, and our cravings and attachments that give rise to dukkha
(suffering). The Dalai Lama (2001) suggests that if, via compassion, we culti-
vate ‘our insight into the miserable nature of life we overcome that attachment’
(p. 85). Schopenhauer also thought that life is pretty horrendous (miserable) which
should inspire us to compassion. Many of the Gothic horror classics, including for
example Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein, were reflections on the horrors of life;
being born without our consent, into bodies designed to age, decay and disease,
in a world where our minds are set up for tribal and self-interest conflicts; yearn-
ing for love and acceptance, which, even if one gets them, are impermanent, with
often painful death waiting in the wings for us and those we love. Death is the only
escape. No wonder the Dalai Lama calls it ‘a miserable life’.
Insight into this reality can lead either to dissonance, hopelessness, despair
and anger, commonly dissociation (just keep these things out of mind and make
the next dollar, plan the next holiday, buy better wine) or compassion, which
is the bodhisattva insight and dedication. On leaving his Golden Palace, it was
these insights (into decay, disease and death) which set Siddhartha on the path to
enlightenment. So here, compassion arises for a deeper focus into the nature of
our reality, and further, that all beings are struggling with this reality, not wanting
to suffer (in a life inherently full of suffering) but be happy (Dalai Lama, 1995). In
many ways some Buddhist concepts are major attacks on our natural tendencies to
dissociate from the harsh realities of the suffering all around us in the very nature
of biological life. In contrast, Western philosophers focus more on the search for
meaning and morality, and medical solutions, rather than happiness and the illu-
sions of the self (Sensky, 2010).
Compassion also implies the prevention of suffering (where we can), which
means addressing needs. So, for example, if we don’t feed our babies, or look after
them they will die and hence suffer. So compassion must involve evaluating and pro-
viding for needs that prevent suffering; indeed we have a range of newly evolved,
socially intelligent competencies that turn a caring motivation into a compassionate
social mentality (see Gilbert, Chapter 3, this volume). To address needs requires
empathic insight into, and taking an interest in, the needs of others. Now, of course,

Page 9
Compassion: definitions and controversies 11
animals can address the needs of their offspring without having deep empathic
insight, but empathic insight along with other socially intelligence competencies
clearly aid our capacity to understand the needs of others and how to address them.
For a bodhisattva ‘a key need’ is to provide conditions for enlightenment.
The point then is that compassion has many textures and definitions which emerge
as partly guided by the functions to which they will be put. We can think of it as a par-
ticular feeling that arises, a motivation to be helpful, a listing of various attributes (of
various types), and linked to personality traits. My own approach has been to focus
on understanding these kinds of dispositions in a functional, evolutionary model
and in particular the way evolved strategies (survival and reproduction) give rise to
motives (see Gilbert, Chapter 3, this volume). In addition I have had an opportunity
to work and meditate with colleagues at Samye Ling Monastery, including Lama
Yeshee and the Buddhist Monk Choden with whom I wrote Mindful Compassion in
2013. Working within motivational theory (Gilbert 1989/2016) and the Mahayana
tradition we have settled on a definition of compassion as ‘a sensitivity to suffering in
self and others with a commitment to try to alleviate and prevent it’.
We added ‘self’ as well as ‘others’, and importantly the concept of ‘pre-
vention’ which is implicit in most models. This actually has two types of
psychology to it. The first is the motivation to attend and engage with suffering
as opposed to avoiding it in various ways. How and why we turn towards or
away from suffering is central to many psychological therapies and even politi-
cal movements. Thus the aspect of motivation to engage is itself a complex
area. Second, we may be motivated to engage but not have much idea of what
to do. So compassion also requires us to think about how we are motivated
to learn how to take action. This can involve courage and also dedication to
understand the causes, prevention and alleviation of suffering so that we take
wise (rather than impulsive or ignorant uninformed) actions. This is why the
model outlined in Chapter 3 tries to identify specific competencies linked to
specific motivation aspects of caring motivation.
In Mahayana tradition this motive underpins Bodhichitta and is supported by
various paramitas – such as generosity, morality, wisdom, patience, energy and
meditation. In the approach outlined in Chapter 3, the motivational approach to
compassion gives a narrative of how it textures our minds. Compassion is rooted
in a motivational care-focused system textured by recently evolved socially
intelligent competencies and it is these competencies that elevate caring into com-
passion (see Gilbert, Chapter 3, this volume).
Conclusion
So where does this leave us? First we see the extraordinary, few thousand year
history that sits behind the concepts of compassion, yet also the way we are reli-
ant on language and cultural contexts to convey meaning. Consequently, different
languages and cultures do not always have exactly the same meaning for the
words they use, and heated debates can arise because people are actually talking

Page 10
12 Paul Gilbert
at cross purposes. Hence, striving for precision and clarity are important, but we
also recognise different definitions for different functions. To date, however, this
precision remains elusive for compassion. There are different definitions, differ-
ent listings of its qualities, with different implications for its study and training.
As mentioned in the Preface we can see this as representing a vibrant, fascinat-
ing area of discussion and scientific enquiry with an agreement that all of us
are a little bit like blind folk touching the elephant. It would therefore be unwise
to prematurely settle on certain definitions without a better understanding of the
processes that underpin compassion, the functions it serves, and allowing better
and more comprehensive definitions to evolve. For example, the way a clinician
may think about compassion might be different to how a lawyer thinks about
compassion. This is not unusual. The way a medical, biologically orientated
psychiatrist, wanting specific drugs for specific symptoms, thinks about depres-
sion and defines it is very different to how a psychodynamic therapist thinks
about depression and defines it. Trying to categorise mental states in simple terms
and lists is notoriously difficult. Anyone familiar with the controversies around
psychiatric diagnosis of what ‘is’ depression, anxiety and paranoia will be very aware
of these issues. What this chapter has tried to do is bring these issues to the fore.
References
Armstrong, R. (2011). Twelve Steps to Lead a Compassionate Life. London: Bodley.
Batson, C. D. (2009). These things called empathy: Eight related but distinct phenomena. In
J. Decety and W. Ickes (Eds.) The Social Neuroscience of Empathy(pp. 3–15). Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Bierhoff, H.-W. (2005). The psychology of compassion and prosocial behaviour. In
P. Gilbert (Ed.) Compassion: Conceptualisations, Research and Use in Psychotherapy
(pp. 148–167). London: Routledge.
Brown, S. L., & Brown, R. M. (2015). Connecting prosocial behaviour to improved
physical health: Contributions from the neurobiology of parenting. Neuroscience and
Biobehavioural Reviews, 55, 1–17.
Cambridge Dictionary (2016). http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/english/compassion.
Cartwright, D. E. (1988). Schopenhauer’s Compassion and Nietzsche’s Pity. Schopenhauer
Jahrbuch, 69, 557–567. http://www.schopenhauer.philosophie.uni-mainz.de/Aufsaetze_
Jahrbuch/69_1988/Cartwright.pdf.
Catarino, F., Gilbert, P., McEwan, K., & Bai�o, R. (2014). Compassion motivations:
Distinguishing submissive compassion from genuine compassion and its association
with shame, submissive behavior, depression, anxiety and stress. Journal of Social and
Clinical Psychology, 33, 399–412. doi: 10.1521/jscp.2014.33.5.399
Condon, P., & Barrett, L. F. (2013). Conceptualizing and experiencing compassion.
Emotion, 13, 817–821.
Cozolino, L. (2006). The Neuroscience of Human Relationships: Attachment and the
Developing Social Brain. New York: W. W. Norton.
Crocker, J., & Canevello, A. (2012). Consequences of self-image and compassionate
goals. In P. G. Devine and A. Plant (Eds.) Advances in Experimental Social Psychology
(pp. 229–277). New York: Elsevier.

Page 11
Compassion: definitions and controversies 13
Dalai Lama. (1995). The Power of Compassion. India: HarperCollins.
Dalai Lama. (2001). An Open Heart. London: Hodder and Stoughton.
Deckers, L. (2014). Motivation: Biological, Psychological, and Environmental. London:
Routledge.
Dutton, J. E., Workman, K. M. & Hardin, A. E. (2014). Compassion at work. Annual
Review of Organizational Psychology and Organizational Behaviour, 1, 277–304.
doi: 10.1146/annurev-orgpsych-031413-091221
Eisenberg, N., VanSchyndel, S. K., & Hofer, C. (2015). The association of maternal
socialization in childhood and adolescence with adult offsprings’ sympathy/caring.
Developmental Psychology, 51, 7–16. doi: 10.1037/a0038137
Ekman, P. (2014). Moving Toward Global Compassion. E-book available from www.
paulekman.com.
Ekman, P. (2016). What scientists who study emotion agree about. Perspectives on
Psychological Science, 11(1), 31–34.
Feldman, C., & Kuyken, W. (2011). Compassion in the landscape of suffering. Contem�
porary Buddhism, 12, 143–155: doi: 10.1080/14639947.2011.564831
Fredrickson, B. L., Grewen, K. M., Coffey, K. A., Algoe, S. B., Firestine, A. M.,
Arevalo, J. M., . . . Cole, S. W. (2013). A functional genomic perspective on human
well-being. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 110, 13684–13689.
doi: 10.1073/pnas.1305419110
Free Dictionary (2016). http://www.thefreedictionary.com/compassion
Gerdes, A. B. M., Wieser, M. J., Alpers, G. W., Strack, F., & Pauli, P. (2012). Why
do you smile at me while I’m in pain?—Pain selectively modulates voluntary facial
muscle responses to happy faces. International Journal of Psychophysiology, 85,
161–167. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2012.06.002
Gilbert, P. (1989/2016). Human Nature and Suffering. London: Routledge.
Gilbert, P. (1998). What is shame? Some core issues and controversies. In P. Gilbert &
B. Andrews (Eds.) Shame: Interpersonal Behaviour, Psychopathology, and Culture
(pp. 3–38). New York: Oxford University Press.
Gilbert, P. (2000). Social mentalities: Internal ‘social’ conflicts and the role of inner warmth
and compassion in cognitive therapy. In P. Gilbert & Bailey, K. G (Eds.) Genes on the
Couch: Explorations in Evolutionary Psychotherapy (pp. 118–150). Hove: Psychology
Press.
Gilbert, P. (2005). Compassion and cruelty: A biopsychosocial approach. In P. Gilbert
(Ed.) Compassion: Conceptualisations, Research and Use in Psychotherapy, pp. 3–74.
London: Routledge
Gilbert, P. (2009). The Compassionate Mind: A New Approach to the Challenge of Life.
London: Constable & Robinson.
Gilbert, P. (2010). Compassion Focused Therapy: The CBT Distinctive Features Series.
London: Routledge.
Gilbert, P. (2015a). The evolution and social dynamics of compassion. Journal of Social &
Personality Psychology Compass, 9, 239–254. doi: 10.1111/spc3.12176
Gilbert. P. (2015b). An evolutionary approach to emotion in mental health with a focus on
affiliative emotions. Emotion Review (special issues Normal and Abnormal Emotion.
K. Scherer (Ed.) 7, 230–237. doi: 10.1177/1754073915576552
Gilbert, P. (2015c). Affiliative and prosocial motives and emotions in mental health.
Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience, 17, 381–389.
Gilbert, P., & Choden (2013). Mindful Compassion. London: Constable & Robinson.

Page 12
14 Paul Gilbert
Godinho, F., Frot, M., Perchet, C., Magnin, M., & Garcia-Larrea, L. (2008). Pain influences
hedonic assessment of visual inputs. European Journal of Neuroscience, 27(9), 2219–2228.
doi: 10.1111/j.1460-9568.2008.06196.x
Goetz, J. L., Keltner, D., & Simon-Thomas, E. (2010). Compassion: An evolutionary analysis
and empirical review. Psychological Bulletin, 136, 351–374. doi: 10.1037/a0018807
Hofmann, S. G., Grossman, P., & Hinton, D. E. (2011). Loving-kindness and compas-
sion meditation: Potential for psychological interventions. Clinical Psychology Review,
31(7), 1126–1132. doi: 10.1016/j.cpr.2011.07.003
Hoge, E. A., Chen, M. M., Orr, E., Metcalf, C. A., Fischer, L. E., Pollack, M. H., . . . Simon,
N. M. (2013). Loving-Kindness Meditation practice associated with longer telomeres in
women. Brain, Behavior, and Immunity, 32, 159–163. doi: 10.1016/j.bbi.2013.04.005
Jazaieri, H., Jinpa, G. T., McGonigal, K., Rosenberg, E., Finkelstein, J., Simon-
Thomas, E., . . . Goldin, P. R. (2013). Enhancing compassion: A randomized controlled
trial of a compassion cultivation training program. Journal of Happiness Studies, 14,
1113–1126. doi: 10.1007/s10902-012-9373-z
Keltner, D., Kogan, A., Piff, P. K., & Saturn, S. R. (2014). The sociocultural appraisals,
values, and emotions (SAVE) framework of prosociality: Core processes from gene
to meme. The Annual Review of Psychology, 65, 425–460. doi: 10.1146/annurev-
psych-010213-115054
Kendell, R. (1975). The Role of Diagnosis in Psychiatry. Edinburgh: Blackwell.
Klimecki, O. M., Leiberg, S., Ricard, M., & Singer, T. (2014). Differential pattern of
functional brain plasticity after compassion and empathy training. Social Cognitive &
Affective Neuroscience, 9, 873–879. doi: 10.1093/scan/nst060
Kogan, A., Oveis, C., Carr, E. W., Gruber, J., Mauss, I. B., Shallcross, A., . . . Keltner, D.
(2014). Vagal activity is quadratically related to prosocial traits, prosocial emotions,
and observer perceptions of prosociality. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
107, 1051–1063. doi: 10.1037/a0037509
Leaviss, J., & Uttley, L. (2015). Psychotherapeutic benefits of compassion-focused
therapy: An early systematic review. Psychological Medicine, 45, 927–945. doi:
10.1017/S0033291714002141
L�pez, A., Sanderman, R., Smink, A., Zhang, Y., van Sonderen, E., Ranchor, A., &
Schroevers, M. J. (2015). A reconsideration of the self-compassion scale’s total score:
Self-compassion versus Self-criticism. PLOS ONE, 10(7): e0132940. doi:10.1371/jour-
nal.pone.0132940
McEwan, K., Gilbert, P., Dandeneau, S., Lipka, S., Maratos, F., Paterson, K. B., &
Baldwin, M. (2014). Facial expressions depicting compassionate and critical emotions:
The development and validation of a new emotional face stimulus set. PLOS ONE,
9(2), e88783.
Mayseless, O. (2016). The Caring Motivation: An Integrated Theory. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Muris, P., & Petrocchi, N. (2016). Protection or Vulnerability? A Meta-Analysis of
the relations between the positive and Negative Components of Self-Compassion
and Psychopathology. Clinical Psychology and Psychotherapy (advanced online).
doi: 10.1002/cpp.2005
Nassbaum, M. C. (2003). Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Neff, K. D. (2003). Self-compassion: An alternative conceptualization of a healthy attitude
toward oneself. Self and Identity, 2, 85–102.

Page 13
Compassion: definitions and controversies 15
Neff, K. D. (2011). Self�compassion. New York: Morrow.
Neff, K. D., & Germer, C. K. (2013). A pilot study and randomized controlled trial of
the mindful self-compassion program. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 69, 28–44.
doi: 10.1002/jclp.21923
Neff, K. D., Whittakar, T., & Karl, A. (in press). Evaluating the factor structure of the
Self-Compassion Scale in four distinct populations: Is the use of a total self-compassion
score justified? Journal of Personality Assessment.
Oxford Dictionary (2016) http://www.oxforddictionaries.com/definition/english/compassion.
Penner, L. A., Dovidio, J. F., Piliavin, J. A., & Schroeder, D. A. (2005). Prosocial behavior:
Multilevel perspectives. Annual Review of Psychology, 56, 365–392. doi: 10.1146/annurev.
psych.56.091103.070141
Preston., S. D. (2013). The origins of altruism in offspring care. Psychological Bulletin,
139, 1305–41.
Ricard, M. (2015). Altruism. The Power of Compassion to Change Itself and the World.
London: Atlantic Books.
Sensky, T. (2010). Suffering. International Journal of Integrated Care, 10, 66–68, ISSN
1568-4156 – http://www.ijic.org/.
Simon-Thomas, E. R., Godzik, J., Castle, E., Antonenko, O., Ponz, A., Kogan, A., &
Keltner, D. J. (2011). An fMRI study of caring vs self-focus during induced compas-
sion and pride. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 7, 635–648. doi: 10.1093/
scan/nsr045
Singer, T., & Bolz, M. (Eds.) (2012). Compassion: Bridging Practice and Science. http://
www.compassion-training.org/
Slavich, G. M., & Cole, S. W. (2013). The emerging field of human social genomics.
Clinical Psychological Science, 1(3), 331–348. doi: 10.1177/2167702613478594
Strauss, C., Taylor, B. L., Gu, J., Kuyken, W., Baer, R., Jones, F., & Cavanagh, K. (2016).
What is compassion and how can we measure it? A review of definitions and measures.
Clinical Psychology Review, 47, 15–27.
Tsering, G. T. (2005). The Four Noble Truths: The Foundation of Buddhist Thought
(Volume 1). Boston, MA: Wisdom Publications.
Weiner, B. (1992). Human Motivation: Metaphors Theories and Research. London: Sage.
Weng, H. Y., Fox, A. S., Shackman, A. J., Stodola, D. E., Caldwell, J. K., Olson, M.C., . . .
Davidson, R. J. (2013). Compassion training alters altruism and neural responses to
suffering. Psychological Science, 24(7), 1171–1180. doi:10.1177/0956797612469537